Click HERE for a link to my current draft of "How To Do Things With Signs: Semiotics in Legal Theory, Practice, and Education."
Abstract
Discussing federal statutes, Justice Scalia tells us that “[t]he stark reality is that the only thing that one can say for sure was agreed to by both houses and the president (on signing the bill) is the text of the statute. The rest is legal fiction."
How should we take this claim? If we take "text" to mean the printed text, that text without more is just a series of marks. If instead we take "text" (as we must) to refer to something off the page such as the "meaning" of the series of marks at issue, what is that meaning and how do we know that all the legislators "agreed" on that "meaning"? In seeking answers here, we necessarily delve into semiotics (i.e., the “general theory of signs”) by noting that meaningful ink marks ("signifiers) signify a meaning beyond themselves (the "signified.") Thus, understanding how signs function is integral to lawyers' textual and linguistic analysis. Additionally, as this article demonstrates, legal analysis and rhetoric are much impoverished if lawyers ignore nonverbal signs such as icons, indices, and nonverbal symbols.
In providing a broad overview of semiotics for lawyers, this article thus (1) begins with a general definition of signs and the related notion of intentionality. It then turns to, among other things, (2) the structure and concomitants of signs in more detail (including the signifier and the signified), (3) the possible correlations of the signifier and the signified that generate signs of interest to lawyers such as the index, the icon, and the symbol; (5) the expansion of legal rhetoric through use of the index, the icon, and the non-verbal as well as the verbal symbol, (6) the nature of various semiotic acts in public and private law (including assertives, commissives, directives, and verdictives); (7) the interpretation and construction of semiotic acts (including contracts as commissives and legislation as directives); (8) the role of speaker or reader meaning in the interpretation and construction of semiotic acts; (9) the semiotics of meaning, time, and the fixation of meaning debate; (10) the impact of signifier drift; (11) the distinction between sense and understanding; and (12) some brief reflections on semiotics and the First Amendment. This article also provides an Appendix of further terms and concepts useful to lawyers in their explorations of semiotics.
Keywords: semiotics, intentionality, signifier, sense, reference, meaning, index, icon, symbol, rhetoric, speech act, interpretation, construction, speaker meaning, reader meaning, originalism, first amendment, intent, contracts, legislation, Peirce, Shakespeare, directive, commissive, verdictive
In addition to law and language generally, this blog explores philosophy, translation, poetry (including my own poetry and translations), legal education reform, genealogy, rhetoric, politics, and other things that interest me from time to time. I consider all my poems and translations flawed works in progress, tweak them unpredictably, and consider the latest-posted versions the latest "final" forms. I'd enjoy others' thoughts on anything posted. © Harold Anthony Lloyd 2024
Showing posts with label Speech Act. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Speech Act. Show all posts
Sunday, January 19, 2020
How To Do Things With Signs: An Overview of Semiotics for Lawyers and Others
Labels:
Charles Sanders Peirce,
Communication,
Experience,
hermeneutics,
Hilary Putnam,
Icon,
Index,
Interpretation,
Language,
Legislative Intent,
Meaning,
Originalism,
Philosophy,
Rhetoric,
Semantics,
Semiotics,
Speech Act
Tuesday, January 30, 2018
Addition to "Strings of Thought" (1/30/18)
Legislative
Intent
1/30/18 Legislative
“intent” lies in legislatures’ speech
acts and not legislators’ speech acts. That is, legislative “intent” is the speaker
meaning of legislatures not legislators—confusing the two is a category
mistake. For example, when the legislature adopts a rule requiring drivers to
drive on the right side of the road, the legislature has performed a directive
speech act adopting a rule to some end or purpose (such as changing driving
patterns to enhance road safety). When
the legislature censures someone, it has performed an expressive speech act
condemning someone for some end or purpose (such as discouraging future bad
behavior on the part of public officials).
The different purposes (and the plans involved in such purposes) distinguish
the different types of speech acts. Recognizing this distinction between legislature and legislator speech acts avoids pseudo-quandaries such as “How can we
ever aggregate the subjective intent of countless legislators to determine
legislative intent?” or “How do we include the intent of a legislator who votes
for a bill for unrelated reasons?” Instead, we ask: “What is the objective bill
or proposal (and the concomitant purpose or plan or both) properly adopted by
the legislature?” We also ask: “What are
the objective concepts involved?” while acknowledging such concepts can have
yet-to-be explored threads and extensions.
1/30/18 A legislature
typically speaks best when it adopts a bill or other proposal (and any
concomitant purpose or plan) after reasonable debate by legislators. Although individual legislators’ speaker meaning in such debates can be highly relevant
evidence of the legislature’s speaker
meaning, legislators’ speech acts are
not legislatures’ speech acts.
The entire post of "Strings of Thought" can be found here.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)