Despite
his limited formal education, Shakespeare’s works display a great deal of legal
knowledge.[1] As a part of Shakespeare’s vast imaginative
universe, his storylines and characters help us (among countless other things) to
analyze the command form of legal positivism, a form of legal positivism
holding that laws are commands of sovereigns backed by threats of punishment.
Various scenarios in the plays help us see how such an approach cannot succeed. As I plan to show in subsequent blogs, Shakespeare
also: (a) beautifully lays out arguments for natural law only to demolish them;
(b) centuries before Holmes formulated his prediction theory of law (the theory
that the law is a set of predictions as to how the courts will act in certain
circumstances), Shakespeare penned plays that help us see how such theory
fails; and (c) Shakespeare otherwise gives us insightful bits and pieces from
which we might begin generating a workable jurisprudence complying with the
semiotics of law and its inherent restraints.[2] In this
first of four planned blogs (all four of which draw from my longer article Let’s Skill
All the Lawyers), I’ll briefly explore the command theory form of legal
positivism using insights from Shakespeare.
A. Law as Sovereign Command
The
command form of legal positivism holds that laws are commands of a sovereign
who is habitually obeyed and who is beholding to none other.[3] If commanded by that sovereign, laws are
valid without regard to their moral content.[4] Instead, they are obeyed to avoid the
predictable punishment that would ensue if they are not obeyed.[5] Shakespeare and logic both make short order
of any such concept of law
B. John, Richard II, Henry IV, Hamlet and
the Problem Of Legitimate Sovereignty
Taking
Shakespeare’s “history plays” in their internal chronological order, The Life and Death of King John (hereafter
King John) explores both the nature
of sovereignty and its legitimacy. In
this play, John has usurped the crown from Arthur,[6] the son of John’s older
brother Geoffrey. Challenging John’s
legitimacy, the Frenchman Chatillon therefore begins the play with a snide reference
to John’s “borrowed majesty.”[7] To complicate matters further, John has an
illegitimate nephew Philip the Bastard.[8]
If
we are using commands and threats as criteria, what makes John and not Arthur or
Philip the Bastard the king? Can’t the latter also issue commands and
threats? Perhaps the difference is that
John is more “sovereign” because more people habitually obey him out of fear of
punishment than they do the other two?
But if so, where do we find John’s legal sovereignty and legitimacy in these
facts alone? How do they distinguish
John from a mere criminal whom the populace habitually obeys out of fear of
physical harm? Certainly kingship
demands something more. John would not
want to be on a par with such criminals, and subjects would not want to be
ruled by criminals. Thus, after MacBeth has lost his ethos as a leader, Angus
notes the loose, unstable feel of such a throne of mere command:
Those [Macbeth]
commands move only in command,
Nothing in love.
Now does he feel his title
Hang loose
about him, like a giant's robe
Upon a dwarfish
thief.[9]
Any “sovereign” who claims no
more legitimacy than the power to sanction if disobeyed must find the garments
of state loose fitting indeed even if most obey him out of fear.[10] As King Lear reminds us, a sovereign
“crowned” only by fear “holds” office only in the sense that a guard dog holds
office over beggars and thieves that flee his bite: “There thou / might’st behold the great image of authority--a
dog's / obeyed in office.”[11] A civilized legal system requires more than a
dog obeyed in office.
C. No Law Without The Biting Dog?
These
problems raise further questions still. What
happens during an interregnum when there is no biting dog? Must not the law disappear between sovereigns
when there is no one to issue commands and threats?[12] Such legal gaps are of course inconsistent
with the rule of law. Furthermore, if
threat of sanction is required for law, what kind of “law” can we have when the
dog exists but doesn’t or won’t bite everyone who “disobeys”? Does this put
some people beyond the reach of the law?
Falstaff, for example, sees himself beyond the law when he sees himself
under no threat of punishment or sanction; he rejoices when Prince Hal is to
succeed Hal’s father Henry IV because Falstaff believes that he can then “take
any man’s horses. . . .”[13]
without threat of sanction. Falstaff easily
understands that criminal acts are effectively decriminalized under such a
theory whenever no realistic threat of sanction exists.[14] Of course, such fluid criminality is hardly
consistent with rule of law. Falstaff is
on to something here but I’d want to say it is a flaw in theory rather than a
license to steal.
D. What if the Commands & Ultimate
Sanctions Come Instead from God?
Might
the command theory work if God himself commands obedience to the earthly
“sovereign” and does so under ever-pending threat of divine sanction? Would the gaps and resemblance to thuggery
then go away? John certainly
attempts this approach. For example, he
tells that “meddling priest,” the pope:
. . . [N]o Italian priest
Shall tithe or
toll in our dominions,
But as we
(i.e., John) under God are supreme head,
So under him
that great supremacy,
Where we do
reign, we will alone uphold,
Without
th’assistance of a mortal hand.[15]
Granting arguendo the existence of such divine commands, has John not
therefore potentially solved his problem?
For if God commands something, must that not legitimize and require the
thing commanded?
The
problem here, of course, is that even if we accept some notion of the divine
right of kings, we cannot as a practical matter determine who holds that right. First, the very disagreement between John and
the supporters of Arthur on its face demonstrates this problem. Second, anyone who would appeal to God as
ground for his office is not only in the awkward position of contradicting
Biblical provisions on the inscrutability of divine will (such as, for example,
the story of Job) but would, like Dido’s sister and Palladas’ thief, reject
much classical wisdom on the subject as well.[16]
Not
surprisingly, John himself ultimately concedes his sophistry. Finding himself
in the end reduced to a wretched figure, he laments as he burns with fever:
There is so hot
a summer in my bosom
That all my bowels crumble up to dust.
I am a scribbled form, drawn with a pen
Upon a parchment, and against this fire
Do I shrink up.[17]
That all my bowels crumble up to dust.
I am a scribbled form, drawn with a pen
Upon a parchment, and against this fire
Do I shrink up.[17]
Failing
to absorb John’s lesson, Richard II also later relies upon divine command as
his source of legitimate authority. As
he puts it:
Not all the
water in the rough rude sea
Can wash the balm off from an anointed king.
The breath of worldly men cannot depose
The deputy elected by the Lord. . . .[18]
Can wash the balm off from an anointed king.
The breath of worldly men cannot depose
The deputy elected by the Lord. . . .[18]
With
the “security” of such “anointing,” Richard II recklessly banishes Henry
Bolingbroke for six years and subsequently confiscates the property of
Bolingbroke’s father, John of Gaunt.
Bolingbroke not surprisingly rebels and raises an army to reclaim his
rights. Still resting on divine rights
despite John’s earlier experience, Richard II philosophically comforts himself:
For
every man that Bolingbroke hath pressed
To lift shrewd steel against our golden crown,
God for his Richard hath in heavenly pay
A glorious angel. Then, if angels fight,
Weak men must fall; for heaven still guards the right.[19]
To lift shrewd steel against our golden crown,
God for his Richard hath in heavenly pay
A glorious angel. Then, if angels fight,
Weak men must fall; for heaven still guards the right.[19]
When further challenged on his
sovereign status as king, Richard exclaims:
If
we be not, show us the hand of God
That hath dismissed us from our stewardship;
For well we know no hand of blood and bone
Can gripe the sacred handle of our scepter,
Unless he do profane, steal, or usurp.[20]
That hath dismissed us from our stewardship;
For well we know no hand of blood and bone
Can gripe the sacred handle of our scepter,
Unless he do profane, steal, or usurp.[20]
Unfortunately for Richard,
real-world experience and social forces push back, and Bolingbroke forces
Richard to abdicate and transfer the throne to Bolingbroke (the future Henry
IV).[21]
Of
course, Bolingbroke (now Henry IV) can find small security in the deed. Having
ousted Richard, Henry IV finds himself back in King John’s same uneasy
state. With John’s and Richard’s
examples as precedent, “victorious” Henry IV must worry about Richard’s earlier
dire prophecy that Bolingbroke has
. . . . come to open
The purple testament of bleeding war.
But ere the crown he looks for live in peace,
Ten thousand bloody crowns of mothers' sons
Shall ill become the flower of England's face,
Change the complexion of her maid-pale peace
To scarlet indignation, and bedew
Her pastor’s grass with faithful English blood.[22]
The purple testament of bleeding war.
But ere the crown he looks for live in peace,
Ten thousand bloody crowns of mothers' sons
Shall ill become the flower of England's face,
Change the complexion of her maid-pale peace
To scarlet indignation, and bedew
Her pastor’s grass with faithful English blood.[22]
Since usurpers
cannot maintain certain sovereignty merely by appeal to God or by physically
seizing the crown, we can expect tumultuous times ahead for those who take such
approaches. Thus, Henry IV laments at
the end of the play that he is full of woe “[t]hat blood should sprinkle me to
make me grow.”[23] He is right to lament. The cycles of earthly and heavenly sovereign
appeal continue their predictably bloody courses through the two parts of King Henry the Fourth, The Life of King Henry the Fifth, the
three parts of King Henry the Sixth,
and The Tragedy of King Richard the Third.
Similar
bloody cycles also play out outside the “history plays.” For example, in The Tragical History of Hamlet Prince of Denmark [hereafter Hamlet], Claudius has murdered the king
(Hamlet's father), married Hamlet's mother and assumed the kingship. Although we might think that God would not
have endorsed such a result, how do we know this with certainty sufficient to
justify the killing of Claudius? How can
Hamlet know that Claudius was not in fact acting out God's will? Hamlet of course cannot know this and,
confounded, he falls into a bloody, downward spiral that leaves, among others,
his mother, Claudius, and himself dead.[24]
E. Falstaff and Amorality
In
addition to the sovereign legitimacy problems generated by sovereign-command
positivism, the theory generates further unacceptable substantive
difficulties. If law is simply the
command of the sovereign given under threat of sanction, then the content is
irrelevant. Evil or nonsensical laws
would be law if they are commanded by the sovereign and are obeyed out of fear
of sanction.
Falstaff,
again, is of course the epitome of one who believes that the sovereign can
command what he will. Thus Falstaff
tells Prince Hal (the future Henry V):
Marry, then,
sweet wag, when thou art king, / let not us that are squires of the night's
body be called / thieves of the day's beauty. Let us be Diana's foresters, /
gentlemen of the shade, minions of the moon; and let / men say we be men of
good government, being gov-/erned as the sea is, by our noble and chaste
mistress / the moon, under whose countenance we steal.[25]
For those interested in the rule
of law, the moral looseness of command-theory positivism is no less troubling
than the other difficulties we encountered above with the theory.
F. Command Theory Insight Through Negative
Example
Shakespeare
not only helps us see how the command theory fails at both the earthly and
heavenly levels. He also helps us learn
from its negative example.
The plays help
us see that any adequate jurisprudence must adequately account for the
symbiotic relationship between the governed and those who govern. Although the notion of the habit of obedience
under threat of sanction fails to account for the law, it does reflect the fact
that no legal system can work if it is not accepted as binding by a sufficient
majority of the “governed.” This proved
a fatal lesson for Richard (at least if one is correct in assuming the “sufficient
majority” was no longer behind him).
Also to this point, Shakespeare’s John foolishly asks, “Doth not the
crown of England prove the king?”[26] No it does not. No matter how securely John physically holds
the physical crown and no matter how many times he might use it to crown
himself “king,” John of course has no practical kingly powers if a sufficient
majority of the governed do not recognize him as their king. Nor, on the
flipside, does John’s physical power to put the crown on his head multiple times
and threaten those who disapprove of the crownings add to any pre-existing
legitimacy. Salisbury’s eloquent words in King
John capture the superfluity:
. . . [T]o be possessed with double pomp,
To guard a title that was rich before,
To gild refinèd gold, to paint the lily,
To throw a perfume on the violet,
To smooth the ice, or add another hue
Unto the rainbow, or with taper light
To seek the beauteous eye of heaven to garnish,
Is wasteful and ridiculous excess.[27]
To guard a title that was rich before,
To gild refinèd gold, to paint the lily,
To throw a perfume on the violet,
To smooth the ice, or add another hue
Unto the rainbow, or with taper light
To seek the beauteous eye of heaven to garnish,
Is wasteful and ridiculous excess.[27]
Additionally,
any jurisprudence which defines law in terms of commands, threats and sanctions
may explain a dog “in office”[28] or
the “authority” of any other menacing figure.
It does not, however, demarcate legitimate legal authority from mere
force or account for interregnal legal continuity—does the law disappear
between kings when there is no king to command and threaten citizens? Rules or standards of legitimacy and continuity
are required for continuity of law and for discernment of applicable law.[29]
In this vein,
H.L.A. Hart in his The Concept of Law
attempts to build a much more sophisticated form of positivism embodying
primary rules governing human conduct as well as secondary rules (a) which
determine which primary rules exist within the system and (b) which govern the
introduction and modification of such primary rules. In this vein as well, Hart also recognizes
the need for the “bulk of society” to internalize the binding nature of
law. Hart understands well that the
physical crown in itself does not “prove the king.” I plan to discuss Hart
further in the blogs that follow.
[1] See Daniel J. Kornstein, Kill All the Lawyers? Shakespeare’s Legal
Appeal xi-xvii (Princeton U. Press 1994);
Mark Andre Alexander, Shakespeare’s
Knowledge of Law: A Journey Through the History of the Arguments, http://www.shakespearefellowship.org/virtualclassroom/Law/index.htm (accessed Dec.
9, 2010). When citing to Shakespeare, my general preference is to use The
Complete Pelican Shakespeare (Orgel & Braunmuller, eds.)
[2] As Shakespeare
will help us see, nothing (including law) is simply given in itself. We impose our own meanings on everything we
study or do. However, as Emily Dickinson
notes, community sets firm semantic limits:
Much Madness is divinest Sense -
To a discerning Eye -
Much Sense - the starkest Madness -
'Tis the Majority
In this, as all, prevail -
Assent - and you are sane -
Demur - you're straightway dangerous -
And handled with a Chain –
Dickinson, Poems of Emily Dickinson (R.W. Franklin, ed.) 278. That is not to say, however, that such
meanings cannot shift or change over time.
They can with proper persuasion thus highlighting the inseparability of
law and rhetoric even at law’s most fundamental levels. For a nice discussion of semantic communities
and their resistance to change, see Robert
Benson, The Interpretation Game 74-75
(2008). By
“semiotics of law” I therefore mean the study of legal terms, provisions and
discourse within their current, generally-accepted semantic framework.
[3] Edwin W.
Patterson, Men and Ideas of the Law 86-87
(1953). Positivism takes on other forms.
For example, H. L. A. Hart defines positivism as “. . . the simple
contention that it is in no sense a necessary truth that laws reproduce or
satisfy certain demands of morality, though they often have done so.” H. L. A.
Hart, The Concept of Law 185-186 (2d
ed., Oxford U. Press 1997).
[4]
Patterson supra n. 3, at 87.
[5] Id. at 86. (Patterson). If one believes in the concept of divine right of
kings, the threat of punishment would also come from an awful cosmic
level. See e.g. Richard II, act 1, sc. 2, lines 37-38 (where Gaunt
refers to Richard II as “God’s substitute” and “His deputy anointed in his
sight).
[6] This is not
factually accurate but serves Shakespeare’s purposes in the play. John’s
brother Richard I actually named John his heir and his succession followed
after some uncertainty. See W. L. Warren, King John 48-50 (1996).
[7] King John, act 1, sc. 1, line 4.
[8] There is no
clear single historical personage corresponding to the Bastard but, again, the
character serves Shakespeare’s purposes in the play. All the political plays contain historical
liberties and I shall correct none further.
I make these initial observations simply to caution the reader to learn
his actual political history of the times from other sources.
[9] Macbeth, act 5, sc. 2 lines 19-22.
[10] This leads us to a further difficulty
with positivism. It is certainly
logically possible to imagine a community with a set of laws which it simply
obeys and which were never promulgated by a sovereign. When Henry V, for example, takes the throne,
he requests the Lord Chief Justice to continue to assist him in application of
the laws of England as he had done for his father Henry IV. See
2 Henry IV, act 5, sc. 3, lines
102-145. Henry V thus realizes that English law is more than edicts of
sovereigns but also includes ancient rights and traditions. Id.
[11] King
Lear, act 4, sc. 5, lines
153-154.
[12] As
Hart points out, interregnum problems under this theory run deeper still. Must not all of a sovereign’s laws die with
him since one cannot obey the dead? Must
there not always be an extended interregnum between “sovereigns” since habits
require time to be acquired? See Hart, supra n. 3, at 52-55.
[13] 2 Henry IV, act 5, sc. 3, line 136.
[14] The
sanction element creates still further problems since many legal acts involve
no sanctions at all (such as procedural or donative transfer laws). See Hart,
supra n. 3, at 27-33.
[15] King John, act 3, sc. 1, lines 153-158.
[16]
Dido’s sister overconfidently believes that Aeneas has come to stay and wed
Dido:
Surely
by dispensation of the gods
And
backed by Juno's will, the ships from Ilium
Held
their course this way on the wind.
Sister,
What
a great city you'll see rising here,
And what a kingdom, from this royal match!
Virgil, The Aeneid 96-97 (Robert Ftizgerald trans., Everyman's Library
1992).
Aeneas was indeed driven by fate and the gods but for a very different purpose
and to a very different end. Dido and
Carthage were but a stop on the way to Aeneas's fated founding of the Roman
race. Palladas similarly points out the
folly of those who claim to know divine will:
They
say Sarapis spoke within a dream
To a killer one night sleeping
underneath
A
failing wall: “Poor wretch, get up and
seek
Another place to sleep.” The man complied.
The
wall collapsed right after he had moved.
His life so spared, the villain then
rejoiced
Believing
that Sarapis must approve
Of murderers. The man gave sacrifice
Of
thanks for his escape when morning came.
Sarapis spoke again to him at night:
“You
think I guard the evil? You escaped
A painless death to die upon a
cross.”
Palladas, The Complete
Palladas 15 (Harold Anthony Lloyd trans., CreateSpace 2010). The hubris of
Dido’s sister and Palladas’ thief ignores the endless other possible
interpretations of their facts just as Jerry Falwell, for example, did in
attributing the September 11 bombings to the wrath of God. See Act Up, Rev. Jerry
Falwell (with Rev. Pat Robertson) blames pagans, abortionists, feminists &
gays and lesbians for bringing on the terrorist attacks in New York and
Washington, http://www.actupny.org/YELL/falwell.html (accessed Nov. 21, 2010).
[17] King John, act 5, sc. 7, lines 30-34.
[18] Richard II, act 3, sc. 2, lines 54-57.
[19] Id. at act 3, sc. 2, lines 58-62. (Richard II)
[20] Id. at act 3, sc. 3, lines 77-81. (Richard II)
[21] Id. at act 4, sc. 1. (Richard II)
[22] Id. at act 3, sc. 3, lines 91-100. (Richard II)
[23] Id. at act 5, sc. 6, lines 45-46. (Richard II)
[24] See generally Hamlet.
[25] 1
Henry IV, act 1, sc. 2, lines 23-29.
[26] King John, act 2, sc. 1, line 273.
[27] Id. at act 4, sc. 2, lines 9-16. (King
John)
[28] King Lear, act 4, sc. 6, lines 153-154.
[29] See Hart, supra n. 3, at 80 (noting that “. . . the ideas of orders,
obedience, habits, and threats, do not include, and cannot by their combination
yield, the idea of a rule, without which we cannot hope to elucidate even the
most elementary forms of law”).
Despite William Shaksper of Stratford's non-existent formal education, Shakespeare’s works display a great deal of legal knowledge.
ReplyDeleteFixed that first line for you.